logo

41 pages 1 hour read

Socialism: Utopian and Scientific

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1880

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part 2Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 2: “Dialectics”

Part 2 Summary

As the title suggests, Part 2 is largely concerned with exploring the dialectical method. Dialectics seek to uncover the truth through a discourse between two or more people holding different viewpoints. Engels begins by presenting Classical Greek dialecticians like Aristotle and Heraclitus. He also describes the dialectical method’s evolution in later work by French and English dialecticians. However, most French philosophers shaping socialist thought were far more concerned with metaphysics than dialectics. Metaphysics is a broad branch of philosophy, but for Engels’s purposes he discusses it to highlight metaphysics’ tendency to apply fixed descriptions to things and ideas in isolation, without acknowledging fluidity or the capacity for a thing to be two or more things at once.

Engels criticizes metaphysics as rigid, narrow, and overly reliant on binaries: “In the contemplation of individual things, it forgets the connection between them; in the contemplation of their existence, it forgets the beginning and end of that existence; of their repose, it forgets their motion. It cannot see the woods for the trees” (55). He poses dialectics as an alternative to metaphysics: “Dialectics, on the other hand, comprehends things and their representations, ideas, in their essential connection, concatenation, motion, origin and ending” (56).

Engels introduces Hegel as another key influence on scientific socialism. Like the utopians in the prior section, Engels highlights the strengths and weaknesses of the Hegelian system. He defines the Hegelian system as such: “In [Hegel’s] system—and herein is its great merit—for the first time the whole world, natural, historical, intellectual, is represented as a process—i.e., as in constant motion, change, transformation, development” (56). To Engels, Hegel’s system is ingenious, but it is limited by his imperfect knowledge pool: Hegel couldn’t know everything, and much of what he did “know” was out of date by Engels’s time. He also disagreed with Hegel’s preference for idealism over materialism.

Nevertheless, by portraying nature and society as a process, the Hegelian system speaks to Engels’s view of socialism. Under old models, history was deemed to be all “irrationality and violence,” compared to the present where idealists strive for utopian perfection. Instead, Engels’s model sees the entirety of history as the “history of class struggles,” which persist to this day. With this revelation, socialism can no longer be thought of as a method of perfecting society, as the utopians believe. Rather, socialism must be seen as a scientific examination of social and economic evolution throughout history for the purpose of ending the class struggles that have defined all previous centuries.

Engels posits that organizing socialism around modern materialism transitions it away from utopianism and into a rational method of truth-seeking. Engels ends the section by praising Marx’s “two great discoveries”—historical materialism and surplus-value—which he says have transformed socialism into a science.

Part 2 Analysis

After identifying the problem with utopian socialists in Part 1, Engels moves on in Part 2 to describe the methodology that leads him to embrace scientific socialism. He rejects metaphysics as too rigid, in that it is based in rigid binaries. Under this model, the past was barbaric, while the present, though still imperfect, is populated by humans who are finally ready to receive socialism as they seek to craft their perfect society. However, Engels implies that history is not a steady arc bending toward progress and equality. Instead, it is constantly in flux and animated by class struggle. For this reason, Engels finds dialectics—the process of synthesizing opposing ideas—a far more convincing paradigm for his purposes than metaphysics.

Hegelian dialectics inform Engels’s views on materialism, in which he goes into greater detail in Part 3. His materialism focuses on the fact that economic conditions dictate historical upheavals. He also identifies a fission in materialist frameworks, that of “old” and “new” materialism. In this dichotomy, he prefers new materialism to old materialism: “Old materialism looked upon all previous history as a crude heap of irrationality and violence; modern materialism sees in it the process of evolution of humanity, and aims at discovering the laws thereof” (59). To Engels, human history, culture, and social arrangements are the result of material processes: they can be identified, evaluated, and described with the same concrete certainty as a chemical process.

Engels’s materialism is supplemented by a proclivity for the Hegelian dialectical method, wherein two opposing assumptions are pitted against each other in the hopes of ascertaining holistic truth. His admiration for the Hegelian philosophical system is not tempered by its ambition; rather, Engels criticizes its failures to meet those ambitions: “That the Hegelian system did not solve the problem it propounded is here immaterial. Its epoch-making merit was that it propounded the problem. This problem is one that no single individual will ever be able to solve” (58).

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
Unlock IconUnlock all 41 pages of this Study Guide

Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.

Including features:

+ Mobile App
+ Printable PDF
+ Literary AI Tools